The many problems with S-representation (and how to solve them)
PDF
HTML

Keywords

Cognitive science
Cognitive representation
Structural representation
Eliminativism
Content

How to Cite

Lee, J., & Calder, D. (2023). The many problems with S-representation (and how to solve them). Philosophy and the Mind Sciences, 4. https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2023.9758

Abstract

The structural representation (S-representation) account provides an increasingly popular way of understanding the role and value of representation in cognitive science. Yet critics remain unconvinced that the account has the resources to rescue representationalism. This paper reviews problems faced by the S-representation account. In doing so, it offers a novel taxonomy that divides objections into two broad camps that ought to be disambiguated: ‘conceptual’ and ‘empirical’. It further shows how these objections can be met, bolstering existing responses in the literature with novel solutions, thus strengthening the S-representation account. Finally, this paper suggests that the types of objections identified provide a generalisable taxonomy for a better understanding of any version of anti-representationalism. Thus, this review is of value to the representation debate more broadly.

https://doi.org/10.33735/phimisci.2023.9758
PDF
HTML

References

Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14(1), 43–64. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515080120033571

Artiga, M. (2022). Strong liberal representationalism. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 21(3), 645–667. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-020-09720-z

Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22, 577–609. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X99002149

Bechtel, W. (1998). Representations and cognitive explanations: Assessing the dynamicist’s challenge in cognitive science. Cognitive Science, 22(3), 295–317. https://doi.org/10.1207/s15516709cog2203_2

Bennett, M., & Hacker, P. (2007). Selections from philosophical foundations of neuroscience. In M. Bennett, D. Dennett, P. Hacker, & J. Searle (Eds.), Neuroscience and philosophy: Brain, mind and language (pp. 3–48). Columbia University Press.

Boone, W., & Piccinini, G. (2015). The cognitive neuroscience revolution. Synthese, 193(5), 1509–1534. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0783-4

Brigandt, I. (2013). Systems biology and the integration of mechanistic explanation and mathematical explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44, 477–492. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2013.06.002

Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/8367.001.0001

Cisek, P. (2007). Cortical mechanisms of action selection: The affordance competition hypothesis. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences, 362(1485), 1585–1599. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2007.2054

Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/1552.001.0001

Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford University Press.

Clark, A. (2015a). Predicting peace: The end of the representation wars—A reply to Michael Madary. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND: 7(R). MIND Group. https://doi.org/10.15502/9783958570979

Clark, A. (2015b). Radical predictive processing. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53, 3–27. https://doi.org/10.1111/sjp.12120

Clark, A. (2016). Surfing uncertainty: Prediction, action, and the embodied mind. Oxford University Press.

Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101(3), 401–431. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01063896

Cummins, R. (1996). Representations, targets, and attitudes. MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/5887.001.0001

Dale, R., Dietrich, E., & Chemero, A. (2009). Explanatory pluralism in cognitive science. Cognitive Science, 33(5), 739–742. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1551-6709.2009.01042.x

Dennett, D. (1975). Why the law of effect will not go away. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 5(2), 169–188. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-5914.1975.tb00350.x

Dennett, D. (2007). Philosophy as naive anthropology: Commment on bennett and hacker. In M. Bennett, D. Dennett, P. Hacker, & J. Searle (Eds.), Neuroscience and philosophy: Brain, mind and language (pp. 73–94). Columbia University Press.

Dolega, K. (2017). Moderate predictive processing. In T. K. Metzinger & W. Wiese (Eds.), Philosophy and predictive processing. MIND Group. https://doi.org/10.15502/9783958573116

Downey, A. (2018). Predictive processing and the representation wars: A victory for the eliminativist (via fictionalism). Synthese, 195(12), 5115–5139. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1442-8

Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. MIT Press.

Duijn, M. van, Keijzer, F., & Franken, D. (2006). Principles of minimal cognition: Casting cognition as sensorimotor coordination. Adaptive Behavior, 14(2), 157–170. https://doi.org/10.1177/105971230601400207

Eliasmith, C., & Anderson, C. H. (2003). Neural engineering: Computation, representation, and dynamics in neurobiological systems. MIT Press.

Facchin, M. (2021a). Predictive processing and anti-representationalism. Synthese, 199(3), 11609–11642. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03304-3

Facchin, M. (2021b). Structural representations do not meet the job description challenge. Synthese, 199, 5479–5508. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03032-8

Figdor, C. (2018). Pieces of mind: The proper domain of psychological predicates. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198809524.001.0001

Fodor, J. (1968). Psychological explanation. MIT Press.

Friston, K. (2009). The free-energy principle: A rough guide to the brain? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13(7), 293–301. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2009.04.005

Gelder, T. van. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation? The Journal of Philosophy, 92(7), 345–381. https://doi.org/10.2307/2941061

Gładziejewski, P. (2015). Explaining cognitive phenomena with internal representations: A mechanistic perspective. Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric, 40(53), 63–90. https://doi.org/10.1515/slgr-2015-0004

Gładziejewski, P. (2016). Predictive coding and representationalism. Synthese, 193(2), 559–582. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0762-9

Gładziejewski, P. (2019). Mechanistic unity of the predictive mind. Theory & Psychology, 29(5), 657–675. https://doi.org/10.1177/0959354319866258

Gładziejewski, P., & Miłkowski, M. (2017). Structural representations: Causally relevant and different from detectors. Biology & Philosophy, 32(3), 337–355. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-017-9562-6

Godfrey-Smith, P. (2006). Mental representation, naturalism, and teleosemantics. In D. Papineau & G. Macdonald (Eds.), Teleosemantics (pp. 42–68). Oxford University Press.

Grice, H. P. (1957). Meaning. Philosophical Review, 66(3), 377–388. https://doi.org/10.2307/2182440

Haselager, P., Groot, A., & Rappard, H. (2003). Representationalism vs. Anti-representationalism: A debate for the sake of appearance. Philosophical Psychology, 16(1), 5–24. https://doi.org/10.1080/0951508032000067761

Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. Oxford University Press.

Hutto, D. (2013). Exorcising action oriented representations: Ridding cognitive science of its Nazgûl. Adaptive Behavior, 21(3), 142–150. https://doi.org/10.1177/1059712313482684

Hutto, D. (2018). Getting into predictive processing’s great guessing game: Bootstrap heaven or hell? Synthese, 195, 2445–2458. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1385-0

Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2012). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262018548.001.0001

Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2017). Evolving enactivism: Basic minds meet content. MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262036115.001.0001

Kiefer, A., & Hohwy, J. (2018). Content and misrepresentation in hierarchical generative models. Synthese, 195(6), 2387–2415. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1435-7

Kirchhoff, M. D., & Robertson, I. (2018). Enactivism and predictive processing: A non-representational view. Philosophical Explorations, 21(2), 264–281. https://doi.org/10.1080/13869795.2018.1477983

Kugler, P. N., Kelso, J. A. S., & Turvey, M. T. (1980). On the concept of coordinative structures as dissipative structures I. Theoretical lines of convergence. In G. E. Stelmach & J. Requin (Eds.), Tutorials in Motor Behavior (pp. 3–47). North Holland. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0166-4115(08)61936-6

Lee, J. (2018). Structural representation and the two problems of content. Mind & Language, 34(5), 606–626. https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12224

Lee, J. (2021). Rise of the swamp creatures: Reflections on a mechanistic approach to content. Philosophical Psychology, 34(6), 805–828,. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2021.1918658

Lycan, W. (1991). Homuncular functionalism meet PDP. In W. Ramsey, S. Stitch, & D. Rumelhart (Eds.), Philosophy and connectionist theory (pp. 259–286). Lawrence Erlbaum.

Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25. https://doi.org/10.1086/392759

McKinstry, C., Dale, R., & Spivey, M. J. (2008). Action dynamics reveal parallel competition in decision making. Psychological Science, 19(1), 22–24. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9280.2008.02041.x

Miłkowski, M., & Litwin, P. (2022). Testable or bust: Theoretical lessons for predictive processing. Synthese, 200(6), 462. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03891-9

Morgan, A. (2014). Representations gone mental. Synthese, 191(2), 213–244. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0328-7

Nirshberg, G., & Shapiro, L. (2020). Structural and indicator representations: A difference in degree, not in kind. Synthese, 198, 7647–7664. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02537-y

Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. MIT Press.

O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2004). Notes toward a structuralist theory of mental representation. In H. Clapin, P. Staines, & P. Slezak (Eds.), Representation in mind (pp. 1–20). Elsevier. https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-008044394-2/50004-X

O’Keefe, J. (1976). Place units in the hippocampus of the freely moving rat. Experimental Neurology, 51(1), 78–109. https://doi.org/10.1016/0014-4886(76)90055-8

O’Keefe, J., & Dostrovsky, J. (1971). The hippocampus as a spatial map. Preliminary evidence from unit activity in the freely-moving rat. Brain Research, 34(1), 171–175. https://doi.org/10.1016/0006-8993(71)90358-1

O’Regan, J. K. (2011). Why red doesn’t sound like a bell: Understanding the feel of consciousness. Oxford University Press.

Orlandi, N. (2014). The innocent eye: Why vision is not a cognitive process. Oxford University Press.

Piccinini, G. (2020). Neurocognitive mechanisms: Explaining biological cognition. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198866282.001.0001

Piccinini, G. (2022). Situated neural representations: Solving the problems of content. Frontiers in Neurorobotics, 16, 846979. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnbot.2022.846979

Ramsey, W. M. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511597954

Ramsey, W. M. (2016). Untangling two questions about mental representation. New Ideas in Psychology, 40(A), 3–12. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.newideapsych.2015.01.004

Ratcliff, R., & McKoon, G. (2008). The diffusion decision model: Theory and data for two-choice decision tasks. Neural Computation, 20(4), 873–922. https://doi.org/10.1162/neco.2008.12-06-420

Remington, E. D., Narain, D., Hosseini, E. A., & Jazayeri, M. (2018). Flexible sensorimotor computations through rapid reconfiguration of cortical dynamics. Neuron, 98(5), 1005–1019. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2018.05.020

Rutar, D., Wiese, W., & Kwisthout, J. (2022). From representations in predictive processing to degrees of representational features. Minds and Machines, 32, 461–484. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-022-09599-6

Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Hutchinson.

Schöner, G. (2019). The dynamics of neural populations capture the laws of the mind. Topics in Cognitive Science, 12, 1257–1271. https://doi.org/10.1111/tops.12453

Segundo-Ortin, M., & Hutto, D. D. (2019). Similarity-based cognition: Radical enactivism meets cognitive neuroscience. Synthese, 1, 98, 5–23. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02505-1

Shagrir, O. (2012). Structural representations and the brain. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63(3), 519–545. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axr038

Shea, N. (2018). Representation in cognitive science. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198812883.001.0001

Sims, M., & Pezzulo, G. (2021). Modelling ourselves: What the free energy principle reveals about our implicit notions of representation. Synthese, 199(3), 7801–7833. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03140-5

Spivey, M. J., Grosjean, M., & Knoblich, G. (2005). Continuous attraction toward phonological competitors. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 102(29), 10393–10398. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0503903102

Sprevak, M. (2011). Representation reconsidered by William M. Ramsey. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(3), 669–675. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axr022

Steiner, P. (2014). Enacting anti-representationalism. The scope and the limits of enactive critiques of representationalism. Avant: Trends in Interdisciplinary Studies, 5(2), 43–86. https://doi.org/10.26913/50202014.0109.0003

Stephen, D., Dixon, J., & Isenhowever, R. (2009). Dynamics of representational change: Entropy, action, and cognition. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 35(6), 1811–1832. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0014510

Thomson, E., & Piccinini, G. (2018). Neural representations observed. Minds and Machines, 28(1), 191–235. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-018-9459-4

Tolman, E. C. (1948). Cognitive maps in rats and men. Psychological Review, 55(4), 189–208. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0061626

Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/6730.001.0001

Wiese, W. (2017). What are the contents of representations in predictive processing? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 16(4), 715–736. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-016-9472-0

Williams, D. (2017). Predictive processing and the representation wars. Minds and Machines, 28(1), 141–172. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-017-9441-6

Williams, D. (2018). Pragmatism and the predictive mind. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 17(5), 835–859. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9556-5

Williams, D., & Colling, L. (2018). From symbols to icons: The return of resemblance in the cognitive neuroscience revolution. Synthese, 195, 1941–1967. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1578-6

Wittgenstein, L. (1953). The philosophical investigations. Blackwell.

Zahnoun, F. (2021). The socio-normative nature of representation. Adaptive Behavior, 29(4), 417–429. https://doi.org/10.1177/1059712320922364

Creative Commons License

This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Copyright (c) 2023 Jonny Lee, Daniel Calder