Abstract
Prominent views about representation share a premise: that mathematical communication theory is blind to representational content. Here I challenge that premise by rejecting two common misconceptions: that Claude Shannon said that the meanings of signals are irrelevant for communication theory (he didn't and they aren't), and that since correlational measures can't distinguish representations from natural signs, communication theory can't distinguish them either (the premise is true but the conclusion is false; no valid argument can link them).
References
Artiga, M. (2021). Signals are minimal causes. Synthese, 198, 8581–8599. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02589-0
Bar-Hillel, Y., & Carnap, R. (1953). Semantic Information. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 4(14), 147–157. http://www.jstor.org/stable/685989
Berger, T., Zhang, Z., & Viswanathan, H. (1996). The CEO problem [multiterminal source coding]. IEEE Transactions on Information Theory, 42(3), 887–902. https://doi.org/10.1109/18.490552
Burge, T. (2010). Origins of Objectivity. Oxford University Press.
Calcott, B., Pocheville, A., & Griffiths, P. E. (2020). Signals That Make a Difference. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 71(1), 233–258. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axx022
Cao, R. (2012). A teleosemantic approach to information in the brain. Biology & Philosophy, 27(1), 49–71. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9292-0
Cao, R. (2014). Signaling in the Brain: In Search of Functional Units. Philosophy of Science, 81(5), 891–901. https://doi.org/10.1086/677688
Cao, R. (2020). New Labels for Old Ideas: Predictive Processing and the Interpretation of Neural Signals. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 11, 517–546. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-020-00481-x
Cover, T. M., & Thomas, J. A. (2006). Elements of Information Theory (2nd ed.). John Wiley & Sons.
de Souza Filho, S. F. (2022). A Dual Proposal Of Minimal Conditions For Intentionality. Synthese, 200(2), 115. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03483-7
Dennett, D. C. (1983). Intentional systems in cognitive ethology: The "Panglossian paradigm" defended. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 6(3), 343–355. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00016393
Dennett, D. C. (2017). From Bacteria to Bach and Back: The Evolution of Minds. Penguin UK.
Donaldson-Matasci, M. C., Bergstrom, C. T., & Lachmann, M. (2010). The fitness value of information. Oikos, 119(2), 219–230. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1600-0706.2009.17781.x
Dretske, F. I. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. MIT Press.
Garson, J. (2019). What Biological Functions Are and Why They Matter. Cambridge University Press.
Godfrey-Smith, P., & Sterelny, K. (2016). Biological Information. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2016, pp. 1–37). The Metaphysics Research Lab. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2016/entries/information-biological/
Gould, J. L. (1975). Honey bee recruitment: The dance-language controversy. Science, 189(4204), 685–693. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1154023
Haldane, J. B. S., & Spurway, H. (1954). A statistical analysis of communication in “Apis mellifera” and a comparison with communication in other animals. Insectes Sociaux, 1(3), 247–283. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02222949
Hunston, S. (2002). Corpora in Applied Linguistics. Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139524773
Isaac, A. M. C. (2018). The Semantics Latent in Shannon Information. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 70(1), 103–125. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axx029
Kelly, J. L. (1956). A New Interpretation of Information Rate. Bell System Technical Journal, 35(4), 917–926. https://doi.org/10.1002/j.1538-7305.1956.tb03809.x
Kolchinsky, A., & Wolpert, D. H. (2018). Semantic information, autonomous agency and non-equilibrium statistical physics. Interface Focus, 8(6), 20180041. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsfs.2018.0041
Lewis, D. (1969). Convention: A philosophical study. Blackwell.
Lombardi, O., Holik, F., & Vanni, L. (2015). What is Shannon information? Synthese, 193(7), 1983–2012. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0824-z
MacKay, D. J. (2003). Information theory, inference and learning algorithms. Cambridge University Press. http://www.inference.org.uk/mackay/itila/book.html
Martínez, M. (2019a). Representations are Rate-Distortion Sweet Spots. Philosophy of Science, 86(5), 1214–1226. https://doi.org/10.1086/705493
Martínez, M. (2019b). Deception as cooperation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 77, 101184. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2019.101184
Maynard Smith, J., & Harper, D. (2003). Animal Signals. OUP Oxford.
Mehta, P., Goyal, S., Long, T., Bassler, B. L., & Wingreen, N. S. (2009). Information processing and signal integration in bacterial quorum sensing. Molecular Systems Biology, 5, 325. https://doi.org/10.1038/msb.2009.79
Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. MIT Press. https://mitpress.mit.edu/books/language-thought-and-other-biological-categories
Millikan, R. G. (1993). White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice. Bradford Books.
Millikan, R. G. (2004). Varieties of Meaning. MIT Press.
Neander, K. (2017). A Mark of the Mental: In Defense of Informational Teleosemantics. MIT Press.
Owren, M. J., Rendall, D., & Ryan, M. J. (2010). Redefining animal signaling: Influence versus information in communication. Biology & Philosophy, 25(5), 755–780. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-010-9224-4
Pandey, B., & Sarkar, S. (2017). How much a galaxy knows about its large-scale environment?: An information theoretic perspective. Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society: Letters, 467(1), L6–L10. https://doi.org/10.1093/mnrasl/slw250
Piccinini, G. (2020). Nonnatural Mental Representation. In J. Smortchkova, K. Dołęga, & T. Schlicht (Eds.), What are Mental Representations? (pp. 254–286). Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190686673.003.0010
Piccinini, G., & Scarantino, A. (2011). Information processing, computation, and cognition. Journal of Biological Physics, 37(1), 1–38. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10867-010-9195-3
Rathkopf, C. (2017a). Neural Information and the Problem of Objectivity. Biology & Philosophy, 32(3), 321–336. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-017-9561-7
Rathkopf, C. (2017b). What kind of information is brain information? Topoi, 39, 95–102. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9512-6
Riley, J. R., Greggers, U., Smith, A. D., Reynolds, D. R., & Menzel, R. (2005). The flight paths of honeybees recruited by the waggle dance. Nature, 435(7039), 205–207. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature03526
Shannon, C. E. (1948). A Mathematical Theory of Communication. Bell System Technical Journal, 27(3-4), 379–423, 623–656. https://doi.org/10.1002/j.1538-7305.1948.tb01338.x
Shannon, C. E., & Weaver, W. (1949). The Mathematical Theory of Communication. University of Illinois Press. http://www.press.uillinois.edu/books/catalog/67qhn3ym9780252725463.html
Shea, N. (2018). Representation in Cognitive Science. Oxford University Press.
Skyrms, B. (2010). Signals: Evolution, Learning, and Information. Oxford University Press.
Woodward, J. (2003). Making Things Happen. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/0195155270.001.0001
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
Copyright (c) 2023 Stephen Francis Mann